Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Judicial Diversity in Ireland: The Need for Gender Equality in the Judiciary, Lecture notes of Law

Diversity and Inclusion in the JudiciaryJudicial AppointmentsLegal Studies in IrelandGender Equality in the Legal Profession

This document examines the issue of judicial diversity in Ireland, focusing on the under-representation of women in the judiciary. The article analyzes various rationales for promoting diversity in the judiciary, including the equity principle and the perspective of legitimacy. The document also discusses the findings of studies on the impact of gender diversity on judging and decision-making.

What you will learn

  • What are the rationales for promoting judicial diversity?
  • Why is judicial diversity important in Ireland?
  • How does gender diversity affect judging and decision-making?
  • What steps can be taken to increase diversity in the Irish judiciary?
  • What are the current statistics on gender representation in the Irish judiciary?

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 08/05/2022

aichlinn
aichlinn 🇮🇪

4.4

(45)

1.9K documents

1 / 17

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download Judicial Diversity in Ireland: The Need for Gender Equality in the Judiciary and more Lecture notes Law in PDF only on Docsity! 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 1 Judicial Diversity in Ireland Dr. Laura Cahillane* Judicial d4iversity is not a subject which is much discussed in Ireland. Despite the fact that our judiciary is still a relatively homogenous group with figures on female judges only recently improving, it seems neither the judges, nor the other two branches of government, see this as an issue which needs to be addressed. This is also in spite of the fact that our current process for appointing judges does not include any incentive or requirement to consider diversity and the recent trend which has seen the appointment of more women to the bench could just as easily be reversed by a future regime. Furthermore, while there has been some improvement in terms of gender balance, it seems there has been no consideration of diversity more generally in judicial appointments. In this context, this article examines whether diversity is an issue which needs to be considered in relation to judicial appointments in Ireland. First, the current profile of the Irish judiciary is illustrated. Then, in order to determine if and why diversity is necessary, the various rationales which have been put forward in favour of judicial diversity are analysed. Finally, the argument in favour of examining this issue in further detail in Ireland is put forward. I - Introduction In January 2014, the Department of Justice initiated a consultation process in relation to the appointment of judges in Ireland. Submissions were invited on issues such as: eligibility for appointment; the need to ensure and protect the principle of judicial independence; promoting equality and diversity; the role of the Judicial Appointments Advisory Board, including its membership and its procedures. Ideas were thus being sought on, amongst other issues, how best to promote equality and diversity in the appointments process. However, somewhat surprisingly, it appears the Irish judiciary themselves do not seem to see diversity as a priority, or even an issue which needs to be addressed.1 For many years in Ireland, the * Lecturer in Constitutional Law in the University of Limerick. 1 While the Judges’ Report to the Department on Reform to the Appointments Process stated that a Commission should be set up to take evidence on issues around diversity and suggests further study could be undertaken, the tenor of the Report was that progress had been made and in the absence of any evidence of a problem, the focus should be on judicial education. The report also stated that: “[i]t is not however apparent that alteration of the structure at the point of appointment to the judiciary addresses a real problem. This is important because any such alteration is complex to devise and operate and creates a difficult intersection with the principle of appointment on the basis of demonstrable merit.” Judicial Appointments Review Committee, “Preliminary Submission to the Department of Justice and Equality’s Public Consultation on the Judicial Appointments Process” (30 January 2014) 21 [hereinafter Judges’ Report], available <http://www.supremecourt.ie/SupremeCourt/sclibrary3.nsf/(WebFiles)/51E71A71B9961BD680257C70005 CCE2D/$FILE/A%20Preliminary%20Submission%20of%20J.A.R.C.%2030.01.2014.pdf> (date accessed: 18 August 2015). 2 Irish Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 6(1) judiciary was one of the most homogeneous groups in the State, comprising mostly white, male, upper-class members and while this is something which has improved markedly in recent years, there is still some way to go in order to achieve an appropriate balance on the bench. However, while the need for diversity and equality in the judiciary has been recognised in some quarters,2 it is not something which is generally accepted in Ireland; it has not prompted any action at policy level and has not generated anywhere near as much discussion as in other common law jurisdictions with similar judicial profiles.3 Neither the media nor the public views this issue as important.4 Furthermore, while the consultation process mentioned above was a welcome initiative, it seems no further action has been taken and is not likely before the next general election. In this context, it is proposed to examine whether diversity is an issue which needs to be considered in relation to judicial appointments in Ireland. First, in order to set the context, the current profile of the Irish judiciary will be established. Then, in order to determine if and why diversity is necessary, the various rationales which have been put forward in favour of judicial diversity will be analysed. Finally, the argument in favour of examining this issue in further detail in Ireland will be put forward. II - The Profile of Judges in Ireland A study conducted in Ireland in 1969 displayed an unsurprisingly congruent picture of the Irish judiciary.5 At the time, there were 57 sitting judges in Ireland. Of these, only one was a woman. Forty-seven percent of all judges and 58% of superior court judges were born in an urban area. Sixty-eight percent lived in Dublin at the time of their appointment. For superior court judges this figure was 94%. Also 59% of all judges and 71% of superior court judges characterised themselves as being upper-middle class. 2 For example, a symposium was held on “Judicial Diversity: Strategies for Change” by the Irish Council on Civil Liberties and Centre for Criminal Justice and Human Rights, U.C.C. (18 September 2008). Also, the Gender Injustice Report highlighted this as an issue, see I. Bacik, C. Costello & E. Drew, “Women in Law – Gender InJustice Report” (Trinity College Law School, 2003). On Northern Ireland, see D. Feenan, “Women Judges: Gendering Judging, Justifying Diversity” (2008) 35 (4) Journal of Law and Society 490. 3 While the situation with regards to diversity is admittedly much worse in England and Wales, this has led to a multitude of academic commentary and policy reports in that jurisdiction. Much work has also been carried out in other jurisdictions such as Canada, South Africa and Scotland but apart from the works mentioned supra note 2, there is a dearth of material here. This very fact was acknowledged in the Judges’ Report. See supra note 1. 4 This has been the personal experience of the author in presenting at conferences and in media interviews related to other judicial matters. 5 P. Bartholomew, The Irish Judiciary (Dublin: I.P.A., 1971). Bartholomew’s study involved “nine Supreme Court judges, eight High Court judges, ten Circuit Court judges, and seventeen of thirty-five sitting District Court judges. Thus forty-four judges comprise the group used to develop this profile of an Irish judge.” 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 5 III - Why do we need a diverse judiciary?15 Various different rationales have been given in answer to questions around the need for diversity. Some are contentious, others less so, but while there does not exist a consensus, it is possible to identify the common and most influential arguments. A. Equal opportunity and fairness One quite obvious rationale is that of equal opportunity and fairness. Lady Brenda Hale has described this rationale as the argument that “all properly qualified and suitable candidates should have a fair crack of the whip and an equal chance of appointment, being considered impartially and solely on their merits and not in some other way or for some other reason.”16 She specifies further that this involves two aspects – process and criteria. By process, Hale is referring to the appointments process itself, and in particular, the now defunct process then operating in the U.K. which was characterised by a “lack of openness, the continuing role of patronage, the dominance of an elite group of chambers and the need to be ‘known’ in order to be appointed.”17 Her arguments about criteria are mainly based on the concept of merit and how this is defined. She also questions the obsession with advocacy as a necessary criterion in the appointments process and asks why there are not more academic appointments. Of course, some of Lady Hale’s criticisms have since been addressed by reforms in the U.K.18 but the more general argument around the necessity for equal opportunity remains. Kate Malleson refers to this argument as the equity principle; the idea that it is inherently unfair that men enjoy a near monopoly of judicial power.19 This idea takes as fact that men and women are equally qualified as judges and that “there are no qualities or characteristics, whether genetic or learnt, which make men better suited to public life and justify their domination of decision-making bodies.”20 Erika Rackley describes the argument as “essentially one of equal opportunities and fairness: all suitably qualified candidates should 15 While these arguments relate to diversity in a general sense, the issue of gender diversity is focused on in particular. 16 B. Hale, “Equality and the Judiciary: why should we want more women judges?” (2001) Public Law 1 at 1 [hereinafter Hale]. 17 Ibid. at 2. 18 At the time she was writing, the process for appointments involved the old “tap on the shoulder” and “secret soundings” methods. These have since been replaced by a more transparent system involving applications to a Judicial Appointments Commission. See Constitutional Reform Act 2005. 19 K. Malleson, “Justifying Gender Equality” (2003) Feminist Legal Studies 1 at 15 [hereinafter Malleson]. 20 Ibid. 6 Irish Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 6(1) have a ‘fair crack of the whip’ when it comes to the process of and criteria for judicial appointment.”21 The principle is almost opposite to the difference argument, outlined below, in that it assumes that women are not necessarily going to transform judicial decision-making but simply that there is nothing about women which makes them less suitable as judicial candidates and thus should not be disadvantaged “by factors which do not relate to their capacity to undertake a particular role.”22 However, it is this very fact which can also be seen as a weakness in the rationale, as Malleson explains. The argument is more concerned “with the interests of the participants rather than society as a whole.” Given that this argument is individualistic rather than societal, Malleson argues that it is not strong enough on its own to promote the need for diversity and thus it is necessary to combine it with “a rationale which demonstrates that equal participation is a prerequisite for the proper functioning of [society]”23 – the idea of legitimacy. B. Democratic Legitimacy Another quite convincing rational is based on the concept of democratic legitimacy, sometimes linked with public confidence in the judiciary and the idea of having a judiciary that is reflective of society. There is much research which points to the general perception of the public that the judiciary is not representative of society; in fact many people believe that the judiciary is out of touch with society – that it comprises a bunch of “pompous old weirdos” who would not understand the workings of the real world.24 The fact is that in order to ensure public confidence in the judiciary, it needs to be more representative of the community as a whole and not “mainly male, overwhelmingly white, [and] largely the product of a limited range of educational institutions and social backgrounds.”25 This does not mean that a judge should represent any particular interests. On the contrary, the idea is that judges remain impartial but that as a diverse group they can better understand and reflect the diverse nature of the community. The argument is similar to that used to justify the current methods of jury selection, which attempt to ensure representation of a fair cross section of the community. 21 Rackley, supra note 12 at 26. 22 Ibid. at 17. 23 Ibid. at 18. 24 See for example, H. Genn, Paths to Justice: What People Do and Think about Going to Law (Oxford: Hart, 1999) at 241. 25 Hale supra note 16 at 10. 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 7 Malleson advances the legitimacy argument on the basis of the “increasing acceptance that the judiciary is a political institution.”26 She explains this as follows: “judges at all levels are exercising power and so are engaged in politics as widely defined. As such, the demands of democratic principles and the need for legitimacy apply to the judiciary as much to any other institution of power ... .”27 Hale has also made a similar argument: [t]he judiciary may or should be independent of government and Parliament but ultimately we are the link between them both and the people. We are the instrument by which the will of Parliament and government is enforced upon the people. We are also the instrument which keeps other organs of the state, the police and those who administer the laws, under control. ... [Therefore,] judges should be no less representative of the people than the politicians and civil servants who govern us.28 Sally Kenney has expanded the legitimacy argument, linking it with the notion of representativeness and using the example of geography in relation to appointment of judges to the E.C.J. She argues that courts, particularly supranational and federal courts, are representative institutions and that issues such as representation of geography, nationality, area of legal expertise and other non-merit factors are often factored into the judicial selection process.29 She points to the fact that E.C.J. includes a judge from each member state and questions whether individual member states would be willing to accept E.C.J. decisions were it not for this fact. It is never argued that judges from the member states are “representing” their member state in the decision-making process but yet it adds to the legitimacy of the Court to have all member states included. Demonstrating the dichotomy between the notions of geographical representativeness and gender representativeness, she asks: [w]hy is it not seen as a deviation from merit to exclude the possibility that the ECJ could consist of twenty-seven German judges but a terrible deviation from merit to prohibit it from being all male? Choosing the best woman judge is not more antithetical to applying Merit standards than choosing the best Cypriot judge. The difference is that requiring diversity of nationality or geography has been accepted as a representative restriction, where gender diversity has not.30 Kenney also refers to the arguments around the inclusion of women in juries to demonstrate the idea of legitimacy. She notes that in discussions around this issue, courts repeatedly say 26 Malleson, supra note 19 at 18. 27 Ibid. 28 Hale, supra note 16 at 10-11. 29 S. J. Kenney, Gender and justice: why women in the judiciary really matter (New York: Routledge, 2013), ch. 6 [hereinafter Kenney]. 30 Ibid. at 128. 10 Irish Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 6(1) different value-systems they have, women will make different, or even better, decisions than male judges.41 Many of these arguments draw on Carol Gilligan’s “ethic of care” theory.42 While this theory is, admittedly, quite persuasive and indeed provides an “almost unanswerable claim for the participation of women in the judiciary”,43 there are many dangers in this approach. The first problem is that despite numerous studies which have been carried out on the question of whether women judge differently, there is no conclusive empirical evidence to support the theory.44 Another problem arises with regard to impartiality; if women judges were to take a more favourable approach to a woman’s evidence or arguments this would not be compatible with the crucial principle of impartiality.45 In one of her earlier articles on this issue, Lady Hale argued similarly “women do not want to claim that they look at things differently from men, partly because this would be manifestly inaccurate in many cases and partly because it would make them less well qualified to be judges”.46 Another problem which impacts directly on women judges is that the difference argument places too great a burden on the women who eventually do ascend to the bench. It “raises the expectation of superiority; women judges can ‘hear’ all the different voices which are raised in court ... .”47 Thus, women judges would have to prove that they are somehow superior – an obviously impossible task. A related objection is that this rationale risks “reifying certain ‘feminine’ ideals perceived as unique to women and fails to account for significant differences between women.”48 Thus it assumes that all women are alike. Finally, the ultimate danger with this rationale is this: “[i]f gender difference is the basis for gender equality, then what happens if it is proved that no significant differences exist? … Or that they do exist but do not improve the quality of justice?”49 It is for these reasons that Malleson argues we should abandon the difference argument and focus on the rationales of equity and legitimacy. 41 See for example, S. Goldman , “Should there be Affirmative Action for the Judiciary?”, (1979) 62 Judicature 489 at 494; I. Grant & L. Smith, “Gender Representation in the Canadian Judiciary”, in Appointing Judges: Philosophy, Politics and Perspective (Toronto: Ontario Law Reform Commission, 1991) 57 at 73; S. McRae, Women at the Top (London: Hansard Society, 1996) at 9; C. McGlynn, The Woman Lawyer: Making the Difference (London: Butterworths, 1998) at 187. 42 See C. Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982). 43 Malleson, supra note19 at 4. 44 Ibid. at 5-7. 45 Ibid. at 9-10. 46 Hale, supra note 16 at 13. 47 Malleson, supra note 19 at 13. 48 D. Feenan, “Women Judges: Gendering Judging, Justifying Diversity” (2008) 35 (4) Journal of Law and Society 490 at 492 [hereinafter Feenan]. 49 Malleson, supra note 19 at 14. 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 11 However, in more recent times, the difference argument has resurfaced in a more nuanced fashion. As Rackley has explained, we should not argue that women judges make a difference but that they bring different perspectives. She elaborates that we should not suggest that women judges speak with a “different voice” but: [p]roperly understood, the promise of judicial difference (however defined) lies in its ability to render the contingent particular but dominant forces of judicial reasoning – that is the incorporation of difference on the bench exposes the extent to which the privileging of particular knowledges, the flattening of difference and the suppression of polytonality both affect and effect women, judging and the delivery of justice.50 The point is that “who the judge is” matters. In 2008, Dermot Feenan published the findings of a survey of women judges in Northern Ireland, which appeared to offer new understandings of the role of judging and which emphasised the distinctiveness of background and experience and demonstrated how this can enhance the diversity rationale.51 The majority of female judges interviewed felt that women judges would make a difference in various ways but not necessarily to the process or outcome of judging. The response of one interviewee sums up the consensus: “[y]ou don’t apply the law any differently, but I do think you see things from a different angle.”52 Even the responses from male judges indicated a recognition of a “difference of perspective”.53 Feenan concluded that the differences that women bring to judging involve “experiential sensitivities that may inform judging.” He noted that the responses did not suggest that women would decide cases any differently, “but their responses also reflect nuances in understanding the role of the judicial office that are not shared by male judges.54 The results are echoed in studies carried out elsewhere which demonstrated differences in the way women judges approach decision-making.55 50 E. Rackley, “What a difference difference makes: gendered harms and judicial diversity” (2008) 15 International Journal of the Legal Profession 37 at 38 [hereinafter Rackley, “What a difference”]. 51 Feenan supra note 48 at 491. The research was conducted during 2004-2005 and involved questionnaires and interviews with a sample of 45 female judges, representing 27% of the total number of female judges. 52 Ibid. at 512. 53 Ibid. at 516. 54Ibid. at 517. 55 See B. Kohn, “Family Judges in the City of Buenos Aires: a view from within” (2008) 15 (1-2) International Journal of the Legal Profession 111. See also M. C. Bellau & R. Johnson, “Judging Gender: Difference and Dissent at the Supreme Court of Canada” (2008) 15 (1-2) International Journal of the Legal Profession 57 at 62. The evidence showed that women did not always share the same perspective but a positioning that left them seeing something different. 12 Irish Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 6(1) While the traditional arguments based on difference, focused on decisional outcomes and essentially reduced law to judgments, this new approach looks at the whole process of judging and the distinctiveness that women and other minorities can bring to this process.56 As Rackley has put it, difference “is not an end in itself but rather a route to engendering diverse perspectives on adjudication, justice and law.”57 Lady Hale has also changed her views on difference. Originally, she was sceptical about the ability of women judges to make a difference, although she always maintained that a more diverse bench “might ... bring about some collective change in empathy and understanding for the diverse backgrounds, experience and perspectives of those whose cases come before them”.58 In 2004, she acknowledged that “the incorporation of difference on the bench subtly changes and, ultimately improves the judicial product”,59 and by 2013, she had come to the view that she and other women judges do actually make a difference: I have come to agree with those great women judges who think that sometimes, on occasions, we may do so (make a difference). That is the result of the lived experience of being a judge for 19 years now and a law lord for nine. Of course, the cases I remember more clearly are the cases where I failed to make a difference, because I failed to persuade my colleagues to see things the same way I did. On those occasions, there is still a benefit in having someone there to voice the minority view, perhaps to lay down a marker for the future, and perhaps to reassure that part of the human race that holds up half the sky that someone up there is listening.60 This more nuanced difference approach is more easily reconciled with the other rationales based on equity and legitimacy.61 Moreover, it provides an even more convincing rationale. As Rackley has commented, “a truly diverse judiciary is not simply apposite (on grounds of, say, equal opportunities or democratic legitimacy) but rather essential if we are to realise the best we possibly can in terms of justice, judgments and judging.”62 56 According to Rosemary Hunter, feminist judges make a difference in four areas: court process, case outcome, reasons given for a decision and extra-curricular activities. See R. Hunter “Can Feminist judges make a difference?”(2008) 15 (1-2) International Journal of the Legal Profession 7. In fact, there is now much research to demonstrate that feminist judges (not necessarily female judges) do make a quantifiable difference in terms of outcome. See for example, R. Hunter, C. McGlynn, & E. Rackley ed., Feminist Judgments: From Theory to Practice (Oxford: Hart, 2010). There are now similar projects in many other jurisdictions which have seen similar results. 57 Rackley, “What a difference”, supra note 50 at 41. 58 Hale, supra note 16 at 9. 59B. Hale, “The Unique Perspectives of Women Judges on the Law” (Bar Reform Lecture, Inner Temple, London, 2004). 60 Ibid. 61 See Feenan, supra note 48 at 518. 62 Rackley, “What a difference”, supra note 50 at 49. See also, Rackley, supra note 12. 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 15 Perhaps the reason why we have not yet had this conversation on the need for judicial diversity in Ireland is because the Irish judiciary wishes to preserve the traditional notions of neutrality and therefore avoid the assumption that judging is more than a technical or mechanical process. If you accept this assumption, that judging is an almost automated action, which is not influenced by background or personal or cultural experience, then there is an argument to be made that diversity is not relevant to judging. However, we cannot avoid the fact that, despite what Justice Cross or the Irish Judges’ Report might indicate, judges are influenced by their backgrounds, experiences and education. In order to embrace the idea of diversity and reconcile the rationales for diversity with the notions of “judging” in Ireland, we first have to recognise that fact. In order to accept the new “difference” rationale or the “different perspectives” rationale, we have to accept that a judge’s perspective matters and in fact is useful in the judicial process.74 To accept the legitimacy argument we have to also accept that courts are representative institutions. We have already accepted this to a certain extent. Lady Hale has pointed to the fact that in the U.K., there is already a requirement to consider geographical diversity, and has questioned why this cannot be extended to other types of diversity.75 In addition, in Northern Ireland, the Judicial Appointments Commission is required “so far as is reasonably practicable to do so, to secure that a range of persons reflective of the community in Northern Ireland is available for consideration by the Commission whenever it is required to select a person to be appointed, or recommended for appointment, to a listed judicial office”.76 In Ireland, there was a convention, now no longer in use, that at least one member of the High or Supreme Court should be drawn from the Protestant community.77 Thus, there are existing precedents where notions of representativeness have been accepted. Even if the notion of representativeness causes discomfort amongst those on the bench, we can always accept Rackley’s suggestion that the judiciary should be a fair reflection of Irish society, which in itself will address the issues with the public’s perception of the judiciary and the issue of justice being seen to be done. 74 See, e.g., the work cited supra note 71. 75 Ibid. Section 27(8) of the Constitutional Reform Act 2005, requires that at the same time as appointing on merit, it must be ensured that “between them, the judges will have knowledge of, and experience of practice in, the law of each part of the United Kingdom.” 76 Justice (Northern Ireland) Act 2002, s.5(10)(b) as amended by the Justice (Northern Ireland) Act 2004, s.3. 77 See D. G. Morgan, Constitutional Law of Ireland, 2nd ed. (Dublin: Roundhall, 1990) at 14. 16 Irish Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 6(1) To accept any of these rationales, it is also necessary to openly recognise that non- merit factors have always been part of the selection process in Ireland. Indeed, it would be difficult to dispute the fact that for many years political allegiance was the most important factor in judicial appointments.78 There is a theory that judges are neutral and objective – the herculean fairy tale – and it seems the Irish judiciary wishes to maintain this fiction. If that were true then perhaps the arguments in favour of diversity would be minimised but the undeniable truth is that judges are human and they do bring their own perspectives to bear when judging; judges, like all other humans, operate from their own perspectives and are influenced by their own experiences and backgrounds – they would not be human otherwise. Judges are certainly not “computers in robes” and nor would we want them to be.79 When judges encounter Dworkin’s “hard cases”, for which there are no rules or straight answers, they must use their own discretion and rely on their own judgment with the benefit of their own life experience. For that reason alone, we need to ensure that we have a wide variety of perspectives and backgrounds being brought to bear on the bench. Perhaps it is time for us in Ireland to let go of the fairy tale and accept that diversity and “who the judge is”80 matters. V – Conclusion It would be easy to point to the recent increase in female appointments to the judiciary as evidence that there are no problems in relation to judicial diversity, at least with regard to gender, in Ireland. However, this is a very cosmetic view of the situation, which accepts that a ratio of about 30:70 women to men in the judiciary is acceptable, and which assumes future governments will be willing to continue this trend. When Ireland’s figures are compared internationally, a more realistic picture emerges: in the 2014 Council of Europe survey on judicial systems, Ireland was placed 7th from the bottom in a table on gender diversity of judicial systems in 47 European countries.81 Furthermore, when the profile of the judiciary is 78 In the Judges’ Report, it was accepted that party political preference has often played a role in appointments and the Report maintained that “it is simply wrong in principle that consideration of political considerations should form any part of the decision process”; Judges’ Report, supra note 1 at 16. 79 M. Minow & E. Spelman, “Passion for Justice” in J. T. Noonan Jr. & K. I. Winston, The Responsible Judge: Readings in Judicial Ethics, (Westpost: Praeger, 1993) 257 at 259-260. 80 See Rackley, “What a difference”, supra note 50 at 41. 81 Council of Europe, European Commission for the Efficiency of Justice Report on European Judicial Systems “Efficiency and quality of justice”, 2014 Edition <http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/cooperation/cepej/evaluation/2014/synthese2014_en.pdf> (date accessed: 14 May 2016). Only the U.K. countries, Armenia, Azerbaijan and Israel were ranked below Ireland. While the data 2016 Judicial Diversity in Ireland 17 more closely examined, we can see that even apart from gender, very little diversity exists within their ranks. Malleson argued in 2003 that, “[i]t is now so widely accepted that the goal of gender equality in … the judiciary … is an unqualified good, that to ask the question why this is necessary seems redundant, if not perverse.”82 However, given the apparent nonchalance of the relevant stakeholders in Ireland, it has been deemed necessary to set this issue out here. Whether or not the difference argument is accepted, it is clear that judicial diversity is a worthwhile goal. This is something which has been recognised in the U.K. and has been reflected in its political agenda for at least the last ten years.83 While in Ireland, our numbers may seem more favourable when compared with those in the U.K., the problem here is that our judicial appointments system does nothing to ensure that the recent trend, which has improved diversity, will continue. In fact, a future Government could well reverse the trend. Interestingly, Lady Hale believes that politicians are more sensitive to this issue than the judiciary and are more likely to address diversity.84 This may be true and while our system, rightly or not, places much power in the hands of politicians, this does not take away the fact that there is currently no requirement to consider diversity. Nor, it seems, is there any political will to examine this issue and set up a taskforce on judicial diversity or some equivalent, as has been done in many other jurisdictions. The means of promoting and achieving diversity is a discussion for another day. Whenever reform to the judicial appointments process is finally tackled in Ireland, it is to be hoped that methods of insuring diversity will be considered, but at the very least, it is to be hoped that judicial diversity will be acknowledged as a worthwhile and necessary pursuit and one that is vital in maintaining public confidence in the judiciary.85 used was from 2012, the closest country above Ireland was Turkey, which had 34.4% women judges and thus would be ahead even using Ireland’s current figures. 82 Malleson, supra note 19 at 1. 83 The Department of Constitutional Affairs 2005 press notice acknowledges this: “[t]he public needs to have confidence in judges who more closely reflect the diversity of the nation, and who have a real understanding of the problems faced by most people.” 84 B. Hale, Lecture given in the University of Limerick (15 May 2015). 85 There is much research to suggest that a judiciary which does not reflect diversity in society damages public confidence. See for example: H. Genn, Paths to Justice: What People Do and Think about Going to Law, (Oxford: Hart, 1999); R. G. Hood, S. Shute & F. Seemungal, Ethnic Minorities in the Criminal Courts: Perceptions of Fairness and Equality of Treatment, Lord Chancellor’s Office 2003, Research Series No. 2/03; R. Moorhead, M. Sefton & L. Scanlan, Just Satisfaction? What Drives Public and Participation Satisfaction with Courts and Tribunals, A Review of Recent Evidence (15 April 2007) <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2425127>.