Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

The Role of Corporate Theory in Supreme Court's Campaign Finance Cases: A Closer Look, Study notes of Constitutional Law

Constitutional LawCorporate GovernanceBusiness LawCampaign Finance Reform

An analysis of the Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission case and the role of corporate theory in the Supreme Court's campaign finance cases. The author discusses the different theories of the corporation, including entity theory, contract theory, process theory, concession theory, and nexus-of-contracts theory. The document also explores how these theories were applied in the Citizens United case and their implications for corporate speech rights.

What you will learn

  • How has the Citizens United decision impacted the SEC's ability to require corporate disclosures?
  • What are the implications of the Citizens United decision for corporate speech rights?
  • What is the significance of the debate about the nature of corporations in campaign finance cases?
  • What are the different theories of the corporation discussed in the document?
  • How was corporate theory applied in the Citizens United case?

Typology: Study notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 07/05/2022

barbara_gr
barbara_gr 🇦🇺

4.6

(72)

1K documents

1 / 34

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download The Role of Corporate Theory in Supreme Court's Campaign Finance Cases: A Closer Look and more Study notes Constitutional Law in PDF only on Docsity! 831 THE SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY IN THE SUPREME COURT’S CAMPAIGN FINANCE CASES Stefan J. Padfield! ABSTRACT In Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, a 5-4 majority of the Supreme Court held that corporate political speech could not be regulated on the basis of corporate status alone. In support of that conclusion, the majority characterized corporations as mere “associations of citizens.” The dissent, meanwhile, viewed corporations as state-created entities that “differ from natural persons in fundamental ways” and “have been ‘effectively delegated responsibility for ensuring society’s economic welfare.’” I have previously argued that these two competing conceptions of the corporation implicate corporate theory, with the majority adopting an aggregate/contractarian view, and the dissent an artificial entity/concession view. Even if one understands Citizens United to be primarily about listeners’ rights, this stark contrast of competing theories of the corporation is difficult to ignore. At the very least, what the majority and dissent thought about corporate speakers was relevant to deciding whether the campaign finance restrictions challenged in Citizens United should fall within that narrow class of speech restrictions justified on the basis of the speaker’s identity due to “an interest in allowing governmental entities to perform their functions.” Somewhat surprisingly, however, the majority was silent, and the dissent expressly disavowed, any role for corporate theory. I have also previously offered some explanations for this apparent inconsistency, and concluded that an active “silent corporate theory debate” was indeed integral to the outcome of Citizens United—despite protestations to the contrary. In this Article, I examine the key Supreme Court cases leading up to Citizens United to see whether a similar silent corporate theory debate is evident in those cases. I find that there is indeed such an on-going debate, and proceed to argue that in future cases involving the rights of corporations, the Justices should make their views regarding the proper theory of the corporation express. This will allow for a more meaningful discussion of the merits of those decisions, and impose an additional layer of intellectual accountability on the jurists. ! Associate Professor, University of Akron School of Law. B.A., Brown University; J.D., University of Kansas. This Article was presented at the Midwest Corporate Law Scholars Conference on June 15, 2011; a faculty workshop at the University of Dayton School of Law on October 11, 2011; the Central States Law Schools Association Scholarship Conference on October 29, 2011; a faculty workshop at the University of Akron School of Law on February 22, 2012; and the Law and Society Association Annual Meeting on June 8, 2012. My thanks to all the participants for their helpful comments. Particular thanks also to Stephen Bainbridge for his comments on the relationship between the director- primacy and real-entity theories of the corporation. 832 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ...................................................................... 832 II. A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE THEORIES OF THE CORPORATION ....................................................................... 835 A. The Entity, Contract, and Process Theories of the Corporation .................................................................... 837 B. Concession and Nexus-of-Contracts Theory .................. 840 III. THE ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY IN THE SUPREME COURT’S CAMPAIGN FINANCE CASES ..................................... 843 A. Citizens United ................................................................... 843 B. The Cases Leading Up to Citizens United ........................ 848 IV. JUDGING CORPORATIONS POST-CITIZENS UNITED .................. 857 V. CRITICISMS OF CORPORATE THEORY’S RELEVANCE ............... 860 VI. CONCLUSION .......................................................................... 863 I. INTRODUCTION In Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, a 5-4 majority of the Supreme Court ruled that corporate political speech could not be regulated on the basis of corporate status alone.1 Given that there is a great deal of debate about what corporations are (corporations have to date eluded capture), one would think that the Court would have needed to answer that question first before reaching its conclusion. However, the majority was silent on this issue and the dissent went so far as to expressly disavow any role for corporate theory at all.2 Instead, the opinion appeared to rest on a “listeners’ rights” analysis.3 It remains unclear, however, how focusing on 1 130 S. Ct. 876, 913 (2010) (“[T]he Government may not suppress political speech on the basis of the speaker’s corporate identity.”). 2 Id. at 971 n.72 (Stevens, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part) (“Nothing in this analysis turns on whether the corporation is conceptualized as a grantee of a state concession, . . . a nexus of explicit and implicit contracts, . . . a mediated hierarchy of stakeholders, . . . or any other recognized model.” (internal citations omitted)). 3 See Larry E. Ribstein, The First Amendment and Corporate Governance, 27 GA. ST. U. L. REV. 1019, 1052–53 (2011) (discussing implications of a listeners’ rights rationale of Citizens United). But see First Nat’l Bank of Bos. v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 828 (1978) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (“It is true . . . that recent decisions of this Court have emphasized the interest of the public in receiving the information offered by the speaker seeking protection. The free flow of information is in no way diminished by the Commonwealth’s decision to Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 835 addressing the role of corporations in society. Nonetheless, I do address some potential criticisms of my proposal in Part V. Finally, I provide concluding remarks in Part VI. II. A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE THEORIES OF THE CORPORATION Robert Hamilton and Richard Booth identify the primary theories of the corporation as: (1) entity theory; (2) concession theory; (3) contract theory; (4) nexus-of-contracts theory (also known as contractarianism); and, (5) “process” theory.9 As I will explain in more detail below, Hamilton’s and Booth’s process theory can be understood to capture both the director- primacy and team-production theories of the corporation.10 One should also understand that concession theory and “artificial entity” theory are essentially synonymous, as are nexus-of-contracts theory and “aggregate” theory. Finally, I will also argue that director-primacy/team-production theory and “real entity” theory are synonymous.11 Because this may all be a bit overwhelming for the uninitiated, I offer the following table for assistance. The reader should take comfort in knowing that at the end of this section we will predominantly be focusing on only two of these theories: concession and nexus-of-contracts. 9 ROBERT W. HAMILTON & RICHARD A. BOOTH, BLACK LETTER OUTLINES: CORPORATIONS 327–32 (5th ed. 2006) (detailing the various theories of corporation law). 10 See generally Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 547 (2003) (describing the director primacy model as it relates to various aspects of corporation law); Margaret M. Blair & Lynn A. Stout, A Team Production Theory of Corporate Law, 85 VA. L. REV. 247 (1999) (arguing for a mediating hierarchy model as a solution to problems inherent in public corporations). 11 As will be discussed in more detail below, both my alignment of director-primacy/team- production with real entity theory, and my conclusion that real entity theory had less of a role to play in Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, 130 S. Ct. 876 (2010), than the contractarianism and concession theory, are at least somewhat controversial. 836 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 THEORY OF THE CORPORATION ALTERNATIVE DESIGNATION BRIEF DESCRIPTION RELEVANT TO OUTCOME IN CITIZENS UNITED? Entity The corporation is a separate legal entity that can, for exam- ple, sue and be sued. No. Concession Artificial Entity The corporation is a creature of the state intended to benefit society as a whole. Yes. The theory posits that the state has wide latitude in regulating its creation. Contract The corporate char- ter represents a con- tract between the state and incorpora- tors. No. Nexus-of-contracts (Contractarianism) Aggregate The corporation is a creature of private contracting. Yes. The theory posits that the state merely provides default rules to facilitate private ordering. Director-primacy & Team Production (Process) Real (Natu- ral) Entity12 The corporate locus of control resides in the board of direc- tors, which focuses on coordinating the interests of all stakeholders. Perhaps, but arguably less so than contrac- tarianism and conces- sion theory. I will first briefly review entity theory, contract theory, and process theory (including director-primacy and team-production theory), before moving on to a more detailed overview of concession theory and nexus-of-contracts 12 See Darrell A.H. Miller, Guns, Inc.: Citizens United, McDonald, and the Future of Corporate Constitutional Rights, 86 N.Y.U. L. REV. 887, 914 n.174 (2011) (“The real entity theory is also known as the natural entity theory.”). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 837 theory. I do this because I believe the entity, contract, and process theories have more limited roles to play in terms of their influence on the campaign finance cases I discuss herein, while the concession and nexus-of-contracts theories represent the two “preeminent” theories of the corporation.13 A. The Entity, Contract, and Process Theories of the Corporation Entity theory simply posits that the corporation is indeed a separate legal entity capable, for example, of being sued and filing suit against others in its own name.14 This is to be contrasted with businesses operating in the general partnership form where, at least traditionally, the partnership was viewed as nothing more than an aggregation of the individual owners.15 Indeed, it is the fact that the corporation stands as a separate legal entity between the owners and third parties that provides at least part of the justification for bestowing limited liability upon the owners.16 As compared to concession theory and nexus-of-contracts theory, however, the fact that the corporation is deemed a legal entity with the right to sue and be sued tells us little about where to draw the line on the state’s authority to regulate corporations. Contract theory, meanwhile, provides that “the charter of a corporation represents a contract (a) between the state and the corporation, or (b) between the corporation and its stockholders, or (c) among the stockholders.”17 This theory was most famously relied upon by the Supreme Court in its Dartmouth College decision, wherein the Court held that the State of New Hampshire would violate the Contracts Clause of the United States Constitution if it unilaterally amended the charter of Dartmouth College 13 Liam Séamus O’Melinn, Neither Contract nor Concession: The Public Personality of the Corporation, 74 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 201, 201 (2006) (describing contractarianism and concession theory as “the two preeminent theories of the corporation”). 14 HAMILTON & BOOTH, supra note 9, at 327–28 (“A corporation may be most readily envisioned as an entity created for the purpose of conducting a business. . . . The entity has the power to . . . bring[] suits or be[] sued . . . .”). 15 Frederick Mark Gedicks, The Recurring Paradox of Groups in the Liberal State, 2010 UTAH L. REV. 47, 55–56 (2010) (“Because corporations are legal entities, the circumstances in which the law will look past the corporation to its individual owners and managers are limited. Because partnerships are not legal entities, however, the situation is reversed: the circumstances in which the law will look to the partnership as an entity, rather than to its owners and managers, are limited.” (footnote omitted)). 16 Thomas C. Folsom, Evaluating Supernatural Law: An Inquiry into the Health of Nations (The Restatement of the Obvious, Part II), 21 REGENT U. L. REV. 105, 148 (2008) (“Limited liability entities are based on the moral intuition of nonagency because there is separation of ownership from control.”). 17 HAMILTON & BOOTH, supra note 9, at 329. 840 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 primacy theories do indeed trace their roots back to contractarianism, it still arguably makes more sense to focus on the more fundamental theory of contractarianism (and its conventional sparring partner: concession theory) before analyzing its various offspring.29 Thus, while all the theories of the corporation described above can be useful, for purposes of this Article I will be focusing on the competing theories of nexus-of-contracts and concession. As Liam O’Melinn has noted, while “[n]ot all theorists use the language of contract and concession,” the two “preeminent” theories of the corporation are the nexus-of-contracts theory and concession theory.30 B. Concession and Nexus-of-Contracts Theory Hamilton and Booth describe concession theory simply as the theory “that a corporation is a grant or concession from the state.”31 Meanwhile, they describe nexus-of-contracts theory as follows: Economists have developed a theory of corporateness that permits analysis of the corporation as an economic phenomenon. This theory rejects the notion that the stockholders are the ultimate owners of the enterprise but treats them, along with bondholders and other creditors, as providers of capital in anticipation of receiving a desired return. The nexus of contracts theory assumes that corporate managers obtain the requirements of the corporation for capital, labor, materials, and services through a series of contractual relationships.32 29 To some extent, this may all be unnecessary hair-splitting because, as I will attempt to show below, the difference between real-entity theory (where I ultimately locate the team- production and director-primacy theories) and contractarianism is potentially inconsequential in terms of the pro-regulatory/anti-regulatory debate because both real- entity theory and contractarianism are typically used to justify deregulation in modern discourse. 30 See supra note 13, at 201 & n.3. See also id. at 258 (discussing “concession theory and . . . its nexus of contracts counterpart”). 31 HAMILTON & BOOTH, supra note 9, at 328. 32 Id. at 330. See generally Melvin A. Eisenberg, The Conception That the Corporation is a Nexus of Contracts, and the Dual Nature of the Firm, 24 J. CORP. L. 819 (1999) (describing the history and limitations of the nexus of contracts conception). In 1976 Michael Jensen and William Meckling first formulated the conception that the corporation is a nexus of contracts . . . . Since that time, the conception has dominated the law-and-economics literature in corporate law. . . . [T]he intellectual history of . . . Jensen and Meckling . . . begins with Ronald Coase[] . . . [who] characterized the boundaries of the firm as the range of exchanges over which the market system was superseded and resource allocation was accomplished instead by authority and direction. . . . Armen Alchian and Harold Demsetz objected to the Coasian conception of the firm, and emphasized instead the role of team production within the firm and the role of agreement and monitoring in team production. . . . Jensen and Meckling applauded Alchian and Demsetz’s objection to Coase’s theory of the firm, but concluded that Alchian and Demsetz had not gone far enough in rejecting Coase . . . . Jensen and Meckling therefore substituted, for Coase’s conception of the firm, the competing Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 841 In differentiating these two theories, it may be helpful to refer to what David Millon describes as the three “dimensions” along which corporate theory has evolved: (1) the corporation as a separate entity versus “a mere aggregation of natural individuals without a separate existence”; (2) the corporation as an “artificial creation of state law” versus a “natural product of private initiative”; and (3) the corporation as a public versus a private construct.33 One may then align concession theory with a view of the corporation as a distinct, separate entity that is a creature of state law serving an ultimately public function, while nexus-of-contracts theory lines up with a view of the corporation as a mere aggregation of natural individuals that is a product of private initiative serving a predominantly private function. One of the key distinctions flowing from all of this is that concession theory tends to support giving the state greater authority to regulate, while nexus-of- contracts theory espouses private ordering. Returning to Hamilton and Booth: According to the nexus of contracts model, it follows that the state should not—and indeed possibly may not—prescribe mandatory rules for corporations by statute that are inconsistent with the express or implicit contracts. The role of corporation statutes, according to this theory, is to provide standardized rules that most corporations will adopt, thereby providing savings for corporations that do not need to incur the cost of independently drafting such provisions.34 Some have suggested that concession theory is no longer viable because it is inexorably tied to a time in history when corporate status was bestowed by the states on a case-by-case basis via a special charter system. For example, Henry Butler and Larry Ribstein have written that “[concession] theory had its origin in the early history of the corporation, when corporations were, in fact, created by special charter. The theory has no relevance today, when corporations are freely formed by making a simple filing under general corporation laws.”35 However, I believe Grant Hayden conception that the firm was a nexus of contracts—and, more particularly, “that most organizations are simply legal fictions which serve as a nexus for a set of contracting relationships among individuals . . . .” Id. at 819–22 (internal footnotes omitted) (quoting Michael C. Jensen & William H. Meckling, Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure, 3 J. FIN. ECON. 305, 310 (1976)) (citing R. H. Coase, The Nature of the Firm, 4 ECONOMICA 386 (1937); Armen A. Alchian & Harold Demsetz, Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization, 62 AM. ECON. REV. 777 (1972)). 33 David Millon, Theories of the Corporation, 1990 DUKE L.J. 201, 201 (1990). 34 HAMILTON & BOOTH, supra note 9, at 330–31. 35 HENRY N. BUTLER & LARRY E. RIBSTEIN, THE CORPORATION AND THE CONSTITUTION, at ix (1995). Larry Ribstein unfortunately and prematurely passed away on December 24, 2011. His impact on the legal academy cannot be overstated. For a truly moving collection of remembrances, visit: Geoffrey Manne, Larry Ribstein, RIP, TRUTH ON THE MARKET (Dec. 24, 2011), http://truthonthemarket.com/2011/12/24/larry-ribstein-rip/. 842 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 and Matthew Bodie espouse the better view when they note that: “One cannot contract to form a corporation. . . . The fact that th[e] permission [to incorporate] is readily granted . . . does not change the fact that permission is required.”36 As I have written elsewhere: [Add together] the ubiquity of reserve clauses in corporate codes, the existence of stakeholder statutes, and relatively recent judicial pronouncements that “[c]orporations are creatures of the Legislature . . . [i]t is appropriate, therefore, that the terms and conditions of their existence be determined by that body,” and I would go so far as to label the argument that concession theory is necessarily tied to our special charter era a straw man.37 Ultimately, anyone who feels compelled to tie the phrase “concession theory” to our special charter era should feel free to replace it herein with something more generic, like “the state-conferred benefits argument.”38 Finally, and as already alluded to above, it is important to note that constitutional law scholars have tended to use a slightly different lexicon when discussing the role of corporate theory in the Supreme Court’s case law. As Reuven Avi-Yonah describes it: Th[e] theories are the aggregate theory, which views the corporation as an aggregate of its members or shareholders; the artificial entity theory, which views the corporation as a creature of the State; and the real entity theory, which views the corporation as neither the sum of its owners nor an extension of the state, but as a separate entity controlled by its managers.39 For myself, I noted that, “while there is obviously much in terms of scholarship that Larry is worth remembering for, what I will primarily remember him for is his inspiring kindness.” Stefan J. Padfield, The Inspiring Kindness of Larry Ribstein, BUSINESS LAW PROF BLOG (Dec. 25, 2011), http://lawprofessors.typepad.com/business_law/2011/12/the- inspiring-kindness-of-larry-ribstein.html. 36 Grant M. Hayden & Matthew T. Bodie, The Uncorporation and the Unraveling of “Nexus of Contracts” Theory, 109 MICH. L. REV. 1127, 1130 (2011) (footnote omitted). Cf. Margaret M. Blair, The Four Functions of Corporate Personhood 4 (Vanderbilt Univ. Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper, Paper No. 12-15, 2012), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2037356 (“The four functions that legal entity status serve would be very difficult, if not impossible, to accomplish using only transactional contracts.”). 37 Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 218 (footnotes omitted) (quoting Neary v. Miltronics Mfg. Servs., Inc., 534 F. Supp. 2d 227, 231 (D.N.H. 2008)) (citing Speir, supra note 20; Orts, supra note 20, at 69). 38 See David G. Yosifon, The Public Choice Problem in Corporate Law: Corporate Social Responsibility After Citizens United, 89 N.C. L. REV. 1197, 1219 (2011) (discussing “The State-Conferred Benefits Argument”); see also Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 218–20 (rejecting Yosifon’s assertion that the state-conferred benefits argument is one of the “‘tempting-but-ultimately-bad’ argument[s] . . . [for] regulating corporate political speech”). 39 Reuven S. Avi-Yonah, Citizens United and the Corporate Form, 2010 WIS. L. REV. 999, 1001 (2010) (emphasis added) (footnote omitted). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 845 the majority’s emphasis on corporation-as-association-of-citizens is consistent with the rhetoric of prior judicial opinions that Avi-Yonah himself identifies as espousing the aggregate (i.e., contractarian) view.53 Second, Avi-Yonah’s suggestion that “association-of-citizens” in Citizens United should be equated with “corporate management working together as an association of persons” because to equate it with the aggregate view would be to align the majority opinion with the shareholder rights argument the majority rejected is belied by the fact that (a) when the government argues that its regulations should be upheld in order to protect shareholders, it is typically best understood as advancing a concession theory argument and thus, “to reject the state’s argument here is to reject concession theory, not the aggregate view,”54 and (b) such a narrow interpretation of “association of citizens” is inconsistent with the much broader use of that phrase in similar contexts by Justice Scalia, whose concurring opinion Avi-Yonah focuses on in making his “association of managers” argument.55 Finally, as far as the dissent is concerned, suffice it to say that I am not alone in seeing concession theory jumping off the pages. Stephen Bainbridge entitled one of his blog posts following the release of the opinion, “Stevens’ Pernicious Version of the Concession Theory.”56 Thus, I agree with Larry Ribstein, who was quoted as saying that “Justice Kennedy’s majority opinion and Justice Stevens’ dissent represent diametrically opposed views of the corporation.”57 Furthermore, the centrality of corporate theory in Citizens United is not negated by the fact that other considerations, like the listeners’ rights rationale mentioned above, were also very important. As Anne Tucker explained: In Buckley and Bellotti, the Court thwarted attempts to restrict corporate political speech on the grounds that (1) speech is money; (2) corporations contribute to the political marketplace of ideas; 53 See Avi-Yonah, supra note 39, at 1013, 1016 (quoting Hale v. Henkel, 201 U.S. 43, 76 (1906); Pembina Consol. Silver Mining & Milling Co. v. Pennsylvania, 125 U.S. 181, 189 (1888); Cnty. of Santa Clara v. S. Pac. R.R. Co., 18 F. 385, 402–03 (C.C.D. Cal. 1883)). 54 See Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 225 (“[I]t is the artificial entity [concession] view, rather than the aggregate view, which favors regulatory solutions.”). 55 See Austin v. Mich. State Chamber of Commerce, 494 U.S. 652, 679 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“‘Attention all citizens. To assure the fairness of elections by preventing disproportionate expression of the views of any single powerful group, your Government has decided that the following associations of persons shall be prohibited from speaking or writing in support of any candidate: _____.’”). 56 Stephen Bainbridge, Citizens United v. FEC: Stevens’ Pernicious Version of the Concession Theory, PROFESSORBAINBRIDGE.COM (Jan. 21, 2010, 4:05 PM), http://www.professorbainbridge.com/professorbainbridgecom/2010/01/citizens-united- v-fec-stevens-pernicious-version-of-the-concession-theory.html. 57 Larry E. Ribstein, Citizens United v. FEC: A Roundtable Discussion, FEDERALIST SOC’Y FOR L. & PUB. POL’Y STUD. (Feb. 3, 2010), http://www.fed-soc.org/debates/ dbtid.38/default.asp. 846 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 (3) there is no special threat of distortion or need to equalize individual and corporate voices; (4) corporate political speech implicates freedom of association rights; and (5) concerns of compelled shareholder speech do not justify restricting corporate political speech. In subsequent cases such as Massachusetts Citizens for Life (“MCFL”) and Austin, however, the Court utilized some of these same arguments to explain or validate certain restrictions on corporate political speech. Later, in Citizens United, however, the Court employed the same lines of reasoning advanced in the cases discussed below, to equalize corporate and individual speech thus expanding corporate First Amendment rights. The Court’s application of these common arguments—as either an attack against or support for corporate political speech restrictions—depends on both the Court’s constitutional conceptualization of corporations and its assumptions about the roles, rights, and responsibilities of corporations in our economic and legal society.58 What then becomes so striking is the majority’s silence on the issue of corporate theory along with the dissent’s express disavowal of any role for corporate theory. Wrote Justice Stevens: “Nothing in this analysis turns on whether the corporation is conceptualized as a grantee of a state concession, . . . a nexus of explicit and implicit contracts, . . . a mediated hierarchy of stakeholders, . . . or any other recognized model.”59 I have written elsewhere that there are a number of possible explanations for this apparent contradiction, including “(1) federalism concerns; (2) a failure to appreciate the significance of corporate theory; and/or (3) a desire to avoid the appearance of imposing unconstitutional conditions on incorporation.”60 As for the federalism concerns, the Supreme Court has itself described corporations as “entities whose very existence and attributes are a product of state law.”61 As I have written elsewhere: “Would the Court now turn around and tell states what they had created?”62 Even with the Court avoiding a direct confrontation on this issue by focusing on listeners’ rights rather than corporate theory, at least some states are still nonetheless pushing back. For example, in Western Tradition Partnership, Inc. v. Attorney General, the Montana Supreme Court upheld state campaign finance laws targeting corporations despite the obvious conflict with Citizens United,63 because “unlike Citizens 58 Tucker, supra note 4, at 509. 59 Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 971 n.72 (2010) (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (citing FRANK H. EASTERBROOK & DANIEL R. FISCHEL, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF CORPORATE LAW 12 (1996); Blair & Stout, supra note 10 )). 60 Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 226–27 (footnotes omitted). 61 CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America, 481 U.S. 69, 89 (1987). 62 Padfield, Citizens United and the Nexus-of-Contracts Presumption, supra note 8, at 27. 63 Western Tradition P’ship, Inc. v. Attorney Gen., 271 P.3d 1, 13 (Mont. 2011). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 847 United, this case concerns Montana law, Montana elections and it arises from Montana history.”64 The majority and dissent in Citizens United may also have simply failed to recognize the significance of corporate theory. In other words, both sides may have felt their view of the corporation was so obviously correct as to not require further discussion. One can perhaps see this perspective in action in the very footnote in which Justice Stevens disavows any role for corporate theory. It is in this footnote that he states as a simple matter of fact that: “It is not necessary to agree on a precise theory of the corporation to agree that corporations differ from natural persons in fundamental ways, and that a legislature might therefore need to regulate them differently if it is human welfare that is the object of its concern.”65 Yet the contention that corporations are fundamentally more than mere associations of citizens, and therefore subject to special regulation, directly implicates concession theory and is precisely the type of conceptualization of corporations that the majority rejected. Finally, the dissent may have been motivated to avoid the issue of corporate theory for fear of setting off an “unconstitutional conditions” debate.66 The majority asserted that: “It is rudimentary that the State cannot exact as the price of those special [corporate] advantages the forfeiture of First Amendment rights.”67 If one understands concession theory to justify state regulation of corporations on the basis of their special status under state law, then avoiding concession theory may allow one to avoid allegations of imposing unconstitutional conditions.68 64 Id. at 6; see also id. at 11 (“The question then, is when in the last 99 years did Montana lose the power or interest sufficient to support the statute, if it ever did.”). Shortly before this Article was finalized, the United States Supreme Court summarily reversed the Montana decision. Am. Tradition P’ship v. Bullock, 132 S. Ct. 2490 (2012) (per curiam). 65 Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 971 n.72 (2010). 66 See 16A AM. JUR. 2D Constitutional Law § 395 (1998) (“The ‘doctrine of unconstitutional conditions’ holds that the government ordinarily may not grant a benefit on the condition that the beneficiary surrender a constitutional right, even if the government may withhold that benefit altogether.”). 67 Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 905 (quoting Austin v. Mich. State Chamber of Commerce, 494 U.S. 652, 680 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting)). 68 But cf. Michael Boardman, Constitutional Conditions: Regulating Independent Political Expenditures by Government Contractors After Citizens United, 10 FLA. ST. U. BUS. REV. 25, 44– 45 (2011) (“[T]he unconstitutional conditions doctrine . . . applies where the government conditions a discretionary benefit with the waiver of a fundamental right . . . . To satisfy the unconstitutional conditions doctrine, the restriction at issue must have a substantial nexus with the purpose of the [benefit]. . . . At face value, restrictions on political speech by government contractors have little to do with the purpose of the contracts themselves—contracts for Lockheed Martin to build airplanes, for example, would not necessarily be substantially related to their right to engage in political speech.”). See generally Darrell A.H. Miller, Guns, Inc.: Citizens United, McDonald, and the Future of Corporate Constitutional Rights, 86 N.Y.U. L. REV. 887, 929 n.278 (2011) (citing 850 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 WRTL would facilitate corruption in a way that justified restriction under the First Amendment.81 Obviously, the Citizens United majority vehemently disagreed that WRTL constituted any sort of a roadblock on its march to invalidate the statute, or that to do so would somehow repudiate WRTL.82 However, there was no identifiable corporate theory dispute in WRTL that would be relevant to our discussion here. 2. Buckley v. Valeo In Buckley, the Supreme Court held that federal statutory provisions limiting individual contributions to campaigns were constitutional, but that provisions limiting individual independent expenditures impermissibly abridged freedom of speech.83 As provided by statute: The term “independent expenditure” means an expenditure by a person—(A) expressly advocating the election or defeat of a clearly identified candidate; and (B) that is not made in concert or cooperation with or at the request or suggestion of such candidate, the candidate’s authorized political committee, or their agents, or a political party committee or its agents.84 Buckley also did not directly address corporate political speech, but constitutes important precedent for Citizens United because it differentiated direct contributions from independent expenditures.85 There is thus little in 81 See id. at 967 n.66 (“[T]he notion that the ‘electioneering communications’ covered by § 203 can breed quid pro quo corruption or the appearance of such corruption has only become more plausible since we decided McConnell. . . . [A]fter WRTL, a corporate or union expenditure could be regulated under § 203 only if everyone would understand it as an endorsement of or attack on a particular candidate for office. It does not take much imagination to perceive why this type of advocacy might be especially apt to look like or amount to a deal or a threat.” (quoting WRTL, 551 U.S. at 465)). 82 Id. at 918 (Roberts, C.J., concurring) (“This case is different—not, as the dissent suggests, because the approach taken in WRTL has been deemed a ‘failure,’ . . . but because, in the absence of any valid narrower ground of decision, there is no way to avoid Citizens United’s broader constitutional argument.” (citation omitted)). 83 Id. at 901–02 (majority opinion) (“The Buckley Court explained that the potential for quid pro quo corruption distinguished direct contributions to candidates from independent expenditures. The Court emphasized that ‘the independent expenditure ceiling . . . fails to serve any substantial governmental interest in stemming the reality or appearance of corruption in the electoral process,’ . . . because ‘[t]he absence of prearrangement and coordination . . . alleviates the danger that expenditures will be given as a quid pro quo for improper commitments from the candidate.’” (citations omitted) (quoting Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 47–48 (1976)). 84 2 U.S.C. § 431(17) (2006). 85 See Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 902 (“Buckley did not consider § 610’s separate ban on corporate and union independent expenditures . . . .”); id. at 954 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (“Buckley famously (or infamously) distinguished direct contributions from independent expenditures, . . . but its silence on corporations only reinforced the understanding that corporate expenditures could be treated differently from individual expenditures. (citation omitted)). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 851 the way of silent corporate theory at work in Buckley. However, the statement in the per curiam opinion that “the concept that government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment,”86 arguably becomes a tool of the aggregate view of the corporation advanced by the majority in Citizens United insofar as corporations are there deemed to be just another “element[] of our society.”87 3. First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti In Bellotti, the Court overturned a criminal statute prohibiting corporations from making expenditures to influence the outcome of a vote on any question other than questions materially affecting the business of the corporation.88 Here, the issue of corporate political speech is front and center, yet there is again no express discussion of particular theories of the corporation.89 Rather, we can see the silent corporate theory debate between contract and concession in some of the language used by the majority and dissent. For example, one can see the contractarian view of corporations as equivalent to other associations of citizens when the majority says: “The inherent worth of the speech in terms of its capacity for informing the public does not depend upon the identity of its source, whether corporation, association, union, or individual.”90 Likewise, the 86 Buckley, 424 U.S. at 48–49. John Rawls focused on this quote in criticizing Buckley: The Court fails to recognize the essential point that the fair value of the political liberties is required for a just political procedure, and that to insure their fair value it is necessary to prevent those with greater property and wealth, and the greater skills of organization which accompany them, from controlling the electoral process to their advantage. JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM: EXPANDED EDITION 360 (2005). See also id. at 359 (“Buckley and its sequel First National Bank [v. Bellotti] are profoundly dismaying.” (citation omitted)). 87 Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 904; see also id. at 957 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (“The majority emphasizes Buckley’s statement that ‘the concept that government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment.’”). 88 First Nat’l Bank of Bos. v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765 (1978). See also id. at 785 n.22 (“We know of no documentation of the notion that corporations are likely to share a monolithic view on an issue such as the adoption of a graduated personal income tax. Corporations, like individuals or groups, are not homogeneous.” (emphasis added)). It should be noted here that it is, however, not too difficult to imagine large swaths of corporations being united in opposing all sorts of cost-imposing regulation. 89 Cf. id. at 823 n.1 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (“[T]he Court today affirms that the failure of [some prior] cases to draw distinctions between artificial and natural persons does not mean that no such distinctions may be drawn. The Court explicitly states that corporations may not enjoy all the political liberties of natural persons, although it fails to articulate the basis of its suggested distinction.”). 90 Id. at 777 (majority opinion). 852 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 contractarian notion that corporations, as mere associations of citizens, start with the presumption of rights akin to other associations (with the burden of proof on those who would limit such rights), can be seen when the majority finds “no support in the First or Fourteenth Amendment, or in the decisions of this Court, for the proposition that speech that otherwise would be within the protection of the First Amendment loses that protection simply because its source is a corporation.”91 Finally, the majority clearly placed itself in opposition to the concession view when it characterized as “extreme” the view that “corporations, as creatures of the State, have only those rights granted them by the State.”92 The Bellotti dissent of Justice White (joined by Justice Brennan and Justice Marshall), on the other hand, employed language very much consistent with a concession view of corporations: Corporations are artificial entities created by law for the purpose of furthering certain economic goals. In order to facilitate the achievement of such ends, special rules relating to such matters as limited liability, perpetual life, and the accumulation, distribution, and taxation of assets are normally applied to them. States have provided corporations with such attributes in order to increase their economic viability and thus strengthen the economy generally. It has long been recognized however, that the special status of corporations has placed them in a position to control vast amounts of economic power which may, if not regulated, dominate not only the economy but also the very heart of our democracy, the electoral process.93 Furthermore, the dissent of then-Justice Rehnquist quoted with approval the language from Dartmouth College that Justice Stevens cited as an example of concession theory in Citizens United:94 Early in our history, Mr. Chief Justice Marshall described the status of a corporation in the eyes of federal law: “A corporation is an artificial being, invisible, intangible, and existing only in contemplation of law. Being the mere creature of law, it possesses only those properties which the charter of creation confers upon it, either expressly, or as incidental to its very existence. These are such as are supposed best calculated to effect the object for which it was created.”95 Thus, it is fair to read Bellotti as embodying the same type of silent corporate theory debate as I have identified in Citizens United. 91 Id. at 784. 92 Id. at 778 n.14. 93 Id. at 809 (White, J., dissenting). See also id. (“The State need not permit its own creation to consume it.”). 94 See Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 971 n.72 (Stevens, J., concurring and dissenting) (citing Dartmouth College as example of concession theory). 95 Bellotti, 435 U.S. at 823 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 855 corruption merely by assuming the corporate form.”103 The majority also expressly tried to recast earlier pro-regulatory opinions as not constituting referendums on the corporate form: “Regulation of corporate political activity . . . has reflected concern not about use of the corporate form per se, but about the potential for unfair deployment of wealth for political purposes.”104 The dissent in MCFL, meanwhile, expressed disappointment at what it saw as the Court turning away from precedent that had acknowledged that the unique state-conferred benefits bestowed on corporations could justify limitations on corporate political speech. Specifically, in Federal Election Commission v. National Conservative Political Action Committee (“NCPAC”),105 the Court had declined to extend NRWC’s restriction of corporate political speech to Political Action Committees (“PACs”). The Court in NCPAC had said: “While in NRWC we held that the compelling governmental interest in preventing corruption supported the restriction of the influence of political war chests funneled through the corporate form, in the present cases we do not believe that a similar finding is supportable . . . . Even assuming that Congress could fairly conclude that large-scale PACs have a sufficient tendency to corrupt, the overbreadth of § 9012(f) in these cases is so great that the section may not be upheld.”106 The MCFL dissent read NCPAC as continuing to recognize what had been, until today, an acceptable distinction, grounded in the judgment of the political branch, between political activity by corporate actors and that by organizations not benefiting from ‘the corporate shield which the State [has] granted to corporations as a form of quid pro quo’ for various regulations.107 Given that the state-conferred benefits argument advanced by the dissent in MCFL is properly aligned with concession theory, MCFL can be read as another case wherein a silent corporate theory debate was at work. 6. Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce In Austin, one of the two main decisions overruled by Citizens United, the Supreme Court held that the unique state-conferred corporate structure 103 Id. at 263. 104 Id. at 259 (footnote omitted). 105 470 U.S. 480 (1985). 106 Id. at 500–01 107 479 U.S. 238, 270 (1986) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (quoting Citizens Against Rent Control v. Berkeley, 454 U.S. 290, 300 (1981) (Rehnquist, J., concurring)); see also id. at 267 (“In light of the ‘special advantages that the State confers on the corporate form,’ . . . we have considered these [anti-corruption and shareholder protection] dangers sufficient to justify restrictions on corporate political activity.” (Rehnquist, J., dissenting)). 856 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 which facilitates the amassing of large treasuries warrants limits on corporate independent expenditures.108 Said the Court: State law grants corporations special advantages—such as limited liability, perpetual life, and favorable treatment of the accumulation and distribution of assets—that enhance their ability to attract capital and to deploy their resources in ways that maximize the return on their shareholders’ investments. These state-created advantages not only allow corporations to play a dominant role in the Nation’s economy, but also permit them to use “resources amassed in the economic marketplace” to obtain “an unfair advantage in the political marketplace.”109 In dissent, Justice Scalia made clear that he viewed distinctions based solely on the corporate form to be insidious because corporations were just one of many types of associations of citizens: “Attention all citizens. To assure the fairness of elections by preventing disproportionate expression of the views of any single powerful group, your Government has decided that the following associations of persons shall be prohibited from speaking or writing in support of any candidate: _____.”110 The contractarian point of view here could not be starker—corporations are literally interchangeable with any other association. 7. McConnell v. Federal Election Commission Finally, in the other major case Citizens United overruled, McConnell v. Federal Election Commission, the Court upheld the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act’s (“BCRA”) extension (via § 203) of § 441b’s restrictions on independent corporate expenditures.111 The majority again relied upon what can fairly be characterized as an artificial entity view: “[W]hether the state interest is compelling—is easily answered by our prior decisions regarding campaign finance regulation, which ‘represent respect for the “legislative judgment that the special characteristics of the corporate 108 Austin v. Mich. State Chamber of Commerce, 494 U.S. 652 (1990). See Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 903 (2010) (“[In Austin,] the Michigan Chamber of Commerce sought to use general treasury funds to run a newspaper ad supporting a specific candidate. Michigan law, however, prohibited corporate independent expenditures that supported or opposed any candidate for state office. A violation of the law was punishable as a felony. The Court sustained the speech prohibition.”). 109 Id. at 658–59. 110 Id. at 679 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 111 540 U.S. 93, 132 (2003) (“BCRA’s central provisions are designed to address Congress’ concerns about the increasing use of soft money and issue advertising to influence federal elections. . . . Title II primarily prohibits corporations and labor unions from using general treasury funds for communications that are intended to, or have the effect of, influencing the outcome of federal elections.”). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 857 structure require particularly careful regulation.”’”112 The dissent, meanwhile, repeated the “mere association” refrain: In Pacific Gas & Electric Co. v. Public Utility Commission of California, . . . we held unconstitutional a state effort to compel corporate speech. “The identity of the speaker,” we said, “is not decisive in determining whether speech is protected. Corporations and other associations, like individuals, contribute to the ‘discussion, debate, and the dissemination of information and ideas’ that the First Amendment seeks to foster.”113 This review of the primary campaign finance cases leading up to, and relied upon in, Citizens United should make clear that an on-going debate about the nature of corporations has been central to the resolution of these cases, despite the fact that none of the opinions have expressly referenced corporate theory. So, what are we to make of this silent corporate theory debate? The answer I propose here is to call on all judges in relevant cases to expressly state their views about which corporate theory is best. This should improve the transparency of judicial opinions, as well as the accountability of judges. What follows is a brief overview of just a couple of the ways the issue of corporate theory continues to make its way before the Court post-Citizens United. The cases discussed demonstrate that, not surprisingly, the status of corporations in our modern society is not an issue that is going to go away any time soon. IV. JUDGING CORPORATIONS POST-CITIZENS UNITED While the Citizens United decision cautions against betting on the corporate theory debate being addressed expressly by the Court any time soon, there should be no shortage of opportunities to challenge the Court on that point, since cases raising the question of what corporations are, and how we should best conceptualize them, are likely to continue to confront the Court with regularity. By way of example, one can examine the case of Federal Communications Commission v. AT&T, which followed Citizens United by little more than a year and examined whether the Freedom of Information Act’s protection of “personal privacy” protects the “privacy” of corporate entities.114 The Court ultimately decided the case on the basis of statutory construction: “‘Person’ is a defined term in the statute [and expressly includes corporations]; ‘personal’ is not. When a statute does not define a term, we typically ‘give the phrase its ordinary meaning.’ . . . ‘Personal’ ordinarily refers to individuals.”115 However, the case simply begs the 112 Id. at 205 (quoting Fed. Election Comm’n v. Beaumont, 539 U.S. 146, 155 (2003)). 113 Id. at 257 (Scalia, J., dissenting in part) (citation omitted) (quoting Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Pub. Util. Comm’n of Cal., 475 U.S. 1, 8 (1986)). 114 131 S. Ct. 1177, 1180 (2011). 115 Id. at 1182 (quoting Johnson v. United States, 130 S. Ct. 1265, 1267 (2010)). 860 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 debate is on-going.”124 Second, even where judges are able to avoid being held accountable in this way because “the application of legal theories is more fact specific, and therefore arguably more imprecise, than their adoption,”125 bringing the clash of corporate theories into the sunlight should nonetheless “serve to illuminate corporate law debates and rarefy the opposing parties.”126 A further potential benefit of having judges expressly adopt particular theories of the corporation in relevant cases is that it may clarify which party has the burden of proof. For example, under the concession theory of the corporation, more of the burden would fall on those seeking to limit the state’s ability to regulate its creations.127 Nonetheless, there are some valid criticisms of my proposal, and I discuss some of them next. V. CRITICISMS OF CORPORATE THEORY’S RELEVANCE Some have suggested that the debate about the nature of the corporation has run its course. Stephen Bainbridge has noted that, “the debate . . . is over . . . . Contractarians and noncontractarians no longer have much of interest to say to one another.”128 However, I would submit that all of the foregoing discussion highlighting the on-going silent corporate theory debate raging in the Supreme Court’s campaign finance cases suggests that contractarians and non-contractarians are still very much engaged. Of course, Bainbridge may more properly be understood to be saying that all the relevant arguments on each side have been fleshed out. Thus, what is merely going on in these cases is fulfillment of the old saw that, while everything’s already been said, it has not yet been said by everyone. 124 Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 228. 125 Id. 126 Verret, supra note 25, at 315. Cf. Roger Martin, Fixing the Game: The Unintended Consequences of an Economic Theory, HUFFINGTON POST (Apr. 27, 2011, 2:40 PM), http://www.huffingtonpost.com/roger-martin/fixing-the-game-the-unint_b_854481.html (“The only way we can avoid increasingly frequent stock market meltdowns—and all the pain, suffering and economic dislocation they cause—is to explore the theories that underpin American capitalism.”). 127 Compare Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 925 (2010) (Scalia, J., concurring) (“Though faced with a constitutional text that makes no distinction between types of speakers, the dissent feels no necessity to provide even an isolated statement from the founding era to the effect that corporations are not covered, but places the burden on petitioners to bring forward statements showing that they are . . . .”), with id. at 950 n.55 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (“Given that corporations were conceived of as artificial entities and do not have the technical capacity to ‘speak,’ the burden of establishing that the Framers and ratifiers understood ‘the freedom of speech’ to encompass corporate speech is, I believe, far heavier than the majority acknowledges.”). 128 STEPHEN M. BAINBRIDGE, CORPORATION LAW AND ECONOMICS 31 (2002) (“[T]he debate has been fully played out.”). Jan. 2013] SILENT ROLE OF CORPORATE THEORY 861 Nonetheless, even here I would posit that new arguments continue to be made. For example, I have argued elsewhere that the official arrival of the too-big-to-fail corporation, which arguably made its grand entrance as a part of the financial crisis of 2008, constituted a new “data point” in the corporate theory debate.129 David Millon presents a further criticism when he argues that: “Historically, the political implications of the natural/artificial and entity/aggregate distinctions have been ambiguous, meaning different things at different times.”130 However, Millon is arguably best understood as warning us about the complexities of corporate theory’s “legitimatizing function,” as opposed to disputing that there is any such function at all.131 In other words, while it may not be possible to tie a particular corporate theory to a particular result in a particular case, corporate theory may nonetheless make a particular outcome more or less likely. This view is consistent with the general alignment of “nexus-of-contracts theory with de-regulation, and concession theory with a fear of the negative consequences of de- regulation.”132 It is also worth noting that Millon was responding to the 129 Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 209–12 (arguing that Dodd-Frank’s official recognition of the too-big-to-fail corporation undermined the majority’s opinion in Citizens United because that opinion rested on a theory of the corporation that espouses a worldview wherein deregulated markets lead to efficiency, not global crisis). 130 Millon, supra note 33, at 202. See also Avi-Yonah, supra note 39, at 1022–23. In 1926, John Dewey published an article in the Yale Law Journal in which he dismisses as irrelevant the debate among the aggregate, artificial entity, and real entity views of the corporation. These views, he explains, could be deployed to suit any purpose; and he uses examples relying on the cyclical nature of these theories. His conclusion is that theory should be abandoned for an examination of reality. Id. (footnotes omitted) (citing John Dewey, The Historic Background of Corporate Legal Personality, 35 YALE L.J. 655, 673 (1926)). Cf. Elizabeth Pollman, Reconceiving Corporate Personhood, 2011 UTAH L. REV. 1629, 1631 (2011) (“[A] metaphor or philosophical conception of the corporation is not helpful for the type of functional analysis that the Court should conduct. The Court should consider the purpose of the constitutional right at issue . . . .”). But see MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW 1870–1960: THE CRISIS OF LEGAL ORTHODOXY 106 (1992) (“[J]ohn Dewey . . . could not, I believe, have demonstrated successfully that each theory of corporate personality could have equally legitimated the practices of emergent large-scale business enterprise.”). 131 See Millon, supra note 33, at 241 (“[P]articular theories of the corporation are perceived to justify particular legal rules or, at a more general level, a particular approach to regulation. Although th[is] legitimation claim is a plausible interpretation . . . the connection between corporate theory and doctrinal and social developments is, in fact, a good deal more complex. We have yet to develop an adequate account of corporate theory’s legitimating function.”). 132 Padfield, The Dodd-Frank Corporation, supra note 6, at 228. See C. T. CARR, THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF CORPORATIONS 165–73 (1905) (describing the concession theory of corporate powers as a response to fears about threats of corporate power to the sovereignty of the King); Joseph F. Morrissey, A Contractarian Defense of Corporate Regulation, 11 TRANSACTIONS: TENN. J. BUS. L. 135, 138 (2009) (“The most problematic 862 JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW [Vol. 15:3 arguments of the esteemed scholar Morton Horwitz, who described corporate theory as having “determinat[ive] normative implications” and playing a significant role in “the legitimation of legal doctrine and social practice.”133 As Horwitz put it: I wish to dispute [the] conclusion that particular conceptions of corporate personality were used just as easily to limit as to enhance corporate power. I hope to show that, for example, the rise of a natural entity theory of the corporation was a major factor in legitimating big business and that none of the other theoretical alternatives could provide as much sustenance to newly organized, concentrated enterprise. . . . [W]hen abstract conceptions are used in specific historical contexts, they do acquire more limited meanings and more specific argumentative functions.134 Ultimately, we need look no further than Citizens United itself for corporate theory’s relevancy. Citizens United’s conclusion that political speech restrictions may not be imposed on the basis of corporate status alone would simply not have been possible under concession theory, which essentially turns on the idea that corporations are different. Rather, the result seemingly requires adoption of the contractarian view that corporations are merely associations of citizens—indistinguishable in any meaningful way from the bevy of other associations that dot the landscape.135 Finally, it can be argued that even if corporate theory is less deterministic than I suggest herein, it nonetheless serves an important legitimization function. That is to say, the average citizen hears the corporate theory story they are being told in these cases whether it is conveyed expressly or not. portion of the nexus-of-contracts framework for me has been the normative claim that many proponents of the framework have proffered: that, because the corporation can be viewed as this bundle of privately ordered contracts, regulation is largely unnecessary and undesirable.” (footnote omitted)). 133 Millon, supra note 33, at 204 (citing Morton J. Horwitz, Santa Clara Revisited: The Development of Corporate Theory, 88 W. VA. L. REV. 173, 221–22 (1985)). 134 HORWITZ, supra note 130, at 68; see also DAVID A. WESTBROOK, BETWEEN CITIZEN AND STATE: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE CORPORATION 135 (2007) (“[A]lthough theories [of the corporation] are not determinative, from time to time and in place to place, they tend to have certain specific associations.”). 135 See Tucker, supra note 4, at 520 (arguing that flawed assumptions about “principles of corporate law or their ensuing realities” led the Court to mistakenly conclude that “corporate political speech is indistinguishable from individual political speech”); see also id. at 505–06 (“[T]ax treatment including the deduction of expenses and the levels of taxation (‘double’ for corporations), issues of criminal punishment, and the application of the commercial speech doctrine primarily to corporate speech are but a few examples of the unique treatment that corporations receive under the law.” (footnote omitted)); Blair, supra note 36, at 9 (“Despite the use of the phrase ‘corporate personhood’ as a summary expression to indicate that a firm has the full package of corporate characteristics, all four characteristics [immortality, entity persona, limited liability, and the separation of ownership and control] actually distinguish corporations from human persons.” (emphasis in original)).